‘Logically alien thought’ and the dissolution of ‘sorites’ paradoxes

 

            For sortal terms, we need a prior -- or at least, a constitutive -- notion of the conditions under which such a term may be properly applied. For example, there must be some condition(s) of distribution for ‘bald’ to apply, and some condition(s) of contiguity for the application of ‘heap’, and so on. How often is this requirement observed, in discussions of the ‘sorites’?

            Discussions of ‘the ‘sorites’ paradox’ typically involve heaps with numbers of grains, or heads-of-hair consisting of numbers of hairs, or the like. But a fairly clear non-case of a heap, such as 100 grains of sand compressed together under extreme force (such that they becomes a tiny lump that takes up only a minute amount of space), or an extremely clear non-case of a heap, such as the same 100 grains (or indeed 1000 or 10000 grains) spread out widely over the floor of a large hall, might well be (or have been) a heap, if arranged appropriately: i.e. if heaped together, loosely. This crucial aspect of what it is to be a heap is unfortunately ignored in most philosophers’ treatments of the matter.[1] Such abstract treatments are vitiated by the omission.

            (An interesting example partly parallel to the example of a heap needing to have a certain amount of physical looseness -- of air -- in it to BE a heap; an example not so often considered; is the vague term, ‘meringue’. A certain amount of egg whipped up but with very little air present will not constiute a meringue; add (in the right way!) a bunch more air, and you have your meringue...)

                                                The point I have made can be extended analogically to most standard sorites paradoxes, probably to all. Think in slightly more detail, for instance, about baldness: it is of course not just the number of hairs, but their arrangement (and also their length, and even their thickness, healthiness, etc.) that crucially matters: Someone whose remaining hair is concentrated in the sideburn area is far more plausibly adjudged bald than someone with a thin spread over the crown...

            Colour terms might be thought to be a counter-example: for don’t colours at least sometimes have a greater simplicity or ‘purity’? We are tempted to say indeed, that colours ‘in themselves’ are simple, unlike states of hair. But think first of actual contexts of use of colour-terms: If I ask for a red car, I don’t expect the tyres or windscreen to be red, but if I ask for a red ball, I expect it to be (pretty) wholly red. On the other hand, if I ask for a red apple, I might be happy if it was only partially red, and I wouldn’t expect its interior to be red; whereas if I wanted my flat painted red, I would expect the paint to be applied to its interior, not its exterior, etc.

            Think secondly of the following kind of observations, made by Wittgenstein in his Remarks on Colour: ‘The bucket which I see in front of me is glazed shining white; it would be absurd to call it ‘grey’ or to say ‘I really see a light grey’. But it has a shiny highlight that is far lighter than the rest of its surface (part of which is turned toward the light and part away from it), without appearing to be a different colour. (Appearing, not just being.).’ [2] From which, Wittgenstein concludes that, ‘The difficulties which we encounter when we reflect about the nature of colour...are embedded in the indeterminateness of our concept of sameness of colour.’ [3] Only if one presupposes that our colour concepts should be determinate -- determinative of their extensions in all instances -- does one generate a soritical paradox in the first place.          

           

            One’s conclusion must surely be that most discussions of sorites paradoxes are dangerously de-contextualised. The paradox in most (perhaps all) cases doesn’t even get off the ground without the de-contextualization. And if one re-contextualizes, if one considers our actual practice, looking carefully for instance at the variety of factors which combine to decide whether or not something is a heap, etc., then philosophical puzzlement largely (even completely) dissolves. Where the only ‘context’ available by contrast is ‘a philosophical discussion’, or ‘a desire to solve ‘the paradox itself’’, then one has condemned oneself to endless debate. When one enables oneself instead to look at how we actually make judgements vis-à-vis vague predicates, then the puzzle (thankfully) dissolves in one’s hands.

            Thus for example the bald question, [I] ‘Is this man bald?’, or even [II] ‘Is this man bald, compared with that man?’, needs to be seen against a background. If this man has a bald patch, and that man has a receding hairline, [II] may be ‘undecidable’. Which counts for more, this or that? Well, it depends what for. The background against which the question is being asked may enable us to decide the answer. (For instance, some monkish religious orders may see a bald patch as perfectly standard, even de rigeur, and thus as little evidence of baldness.) The desire for context-independent answers to questions like [I] and [II] is as one with the desire to solve the sorites paradox ‘itself’. It is a desire we need to grow out of.

 

            Some readers will not yet be fully satisfied. They will still perhaps be feeling the pull of the paradox; the general pull, that is, towards thinking that vagueness poses a philosophical problem that will not happily dissolve. They will be inclined to the very abstraction that I am warning against. Let me try to satisfy them by making first a kind of concession ... by moving away somewhat further from the actual world and actual (concrete, unconfused, non-metaphysical [4] ) language use: there certainly is a role in the consideration of the sorites for perhaps-peculiar ‘thought experiments’. We can enrich ‘our diet of examples’ appropriately by considering not just ways in which we might physically arrange and manipulate grains of sand to produce cases that tug revealingly on our ‘intuitions’ about heaphood, but by considering possible radically alternative socio-linguistic practices involving heaps.

 

            Take a famous example from Wittgenstein’s corpus: his ‘woodsellers’.[5] These people, who seem to regard wood piled into heaps as having less quantity (and thus as worth or costing less than) wood that is spread out to cover a greater area on the ground, have typically been taken by Wittgenstein’s ‘critics’ as plain stupid/irrational, or alternatively as manifesting a conceptual impossibility. By Wittgenstein’s ‘followers’, they have been typically taken to demonstrate a true conceptual relativism, a possible radically-other ‘form of life’.

            For reasons that will become clearer,[6] these responses seem to me unsatisfactory. Perhaps, though, it is already evident how we might recast the strange ‘woodsellers’: perhaps they are a (perhaps-conceivable) would-be real example of the kind of reasoning I displayed in the opening paragraphs of this paper, above. Perhaps the correct way to ‘paraphrase’ the woodsellers’ talk, to render them happily less deeply-strange, is to hear them as talking about heaps. Perhaps they have an evaluative attitude to heaps of wood of very roughly the kind that (though with a roughly opposite ‘valence’ to) that we have to meringues. At least in this sense: how those heaps are ‘made’, or arranged, is of deep import to these people. Specifically, in this case: if the planks of wood (compare grains of sand) are de-heaped, though without being completely scattered, they gain value for these people.

            If this were right, then the woodsellers need not be sub-human,[7] nor oxymoronic or impossible, nor even so different that we really cannot speak of them intelligibly (such that they would not properly even be termed people at all). They have significantly different preferences or values from us (so far at least as wood is concerned), but they do not pose a problem of ‘conceptual relativity’, with all the terrible philosophical problems that that brings in its wake.[8] 

            I think that my suggestion is a live option when reading Wittgenstein’s ‘woodsellers’ scenario. It brings into prominence that most philosophers have tended only to consider a crude set of options, when confronted with this intriguing and difficult text of Wittgenstein’s. Rarely has anyone attempted to give, as I have here, a way of filling out Wittgenstein’s vague (!), lightly-specified ‘object of comparison’ such that these strangers would retain their difference without being alien to the point of madness or sub-human-ness, etc. . The woodsellers, from my perspective, can be read as different without having to be read, impossibly and absurdly, as ‘logical aliens’.[9]  And comparing the woodsellers’ case to our own can yield insights into the (limited[10]) degree to which we can intelligibly relax the constraints on what we remain willing to call ‘mathematics’, and similarly fundamental aspects of our world-view, of our life.

            But the particular way of taking forward the comparison essayed here has the added virtue of helping to dissolve the pull on one of soritical reasoning. The ‘concession’ I made above turns out to have helped my case, not hindered it.

 

            Let me then try to sum up the point that we have now reached. My argument does not, I believe, contradict the reasoning of ‘New Wittgensteinian’ authors (such as James Conant, Alice Crary and David Cerbone) who have argued that perhaps the most crucial (and all-too-rarely-understood) aspect of ‘scenarios’ of Wittgenstein’s such as that of the ‘builders’ and the ‘woodsellers’ is that Wittgenstein intends for them to collapse under the philosophical weight we are tempted, in reading his work, to try to make them bear. The builders and the woodsellers, philosophically-speaking, yield only houses of air, whose collapse leaves no more than empty rubble behind... When Wittgensteinian considerations dissolve Frege’s notion of illogical thought -- a kind of thought that would be ‘radically’ different from our own, which is yet a kind of thought -- into nothingness, nothing useful remains in the idea that we may have thought we had of logically-alien thought: of (e.g.) a ‘wholly’ different mathematics which is yet a mathematics. But Wittgenstein’s text, I would maintain, also leaves it open whether there can be anybody whom we might on reflection want to call ‘mathematical strangers’. We might indeed, that is, call the woodsellers as I have interpreted them ‘mathematical strangers’, even ‘very-strangers’, but not need to see them as posing a problem of embodying logically alien thought. There can be a reading of the woodsellers wherein they could be actual -- and would not pose a philosophical problem for anyone with any sensible take on these matters.[11]

            In short, I have begun to supply above, I believe, a slightly more-detailed scenario than Wittgenstein’s own, a scenario that fills out his ‘example’ in a way that gives it sense. The appearance of contradiction or paradox in the description of the woodsellers can be dissolved, if we treat them as part of a dissolution of the would-be paradox of the heap.

 

            It is very important not to assimilate what I have done so far to any form of objectionable conceptual relativism or anti-realism. My argument does not amount to the claim that a heap is no more than what we choose to call a heap. Nor does what I have done here amount to a form of philosophical quietism.[12] My argument does not leave intact a pressing philosophical problem of what is to count as baldness or ‘heapness’ that it simply refuses to address. Far from it. To see why neither of these charges is apposite, it is enough I think to recall the following remarks of Wittgenstein’s:

 

                ‘[S]omeone might object against me: ‘You take the easy way out! You talk about all sorts of language-games, but have nowhere said what the essence of a language-game, and hence of language, is: what is common to all these activities, and what makes them into language or parts of language...’

                And this is true.__Instead of producing something common to all that we call language, I am saying that these phenomena have no one thing in common which makes us use the same word for all,__ but that they are related to one another in many different ways. And it is because of this relationship, or these relationships, that we call them all ‘language’.’ [13]

 

I do not have to tell you what counts as baldness, any more than I have to tell you what counts as ‘game-ness’. If you are a competent practitioner of English, you  know. Yet, as the underlined sentence above -- a sentence so often ignored in accounts of Wittgenstein on ‘family-resemblance’, even, regrettably, by would-be Wittgensteinians -- makes clear, there is no form of anti-realism here. It is the relationships of cases of baldness to one another, their complicatedly overlapping resemblances, that is the ‘basis’ for our understanding of what are and what are not cases of baldness. The game-ness of games is ‘surveyably’ open to all; if you insist on continuing to ask what it is that makes games games, the best and only needful answer available is: it is the similarities of games to one another that makes them games.[14] The edges of this concept are variable (over time and space) and indeed we might well call them vague, but this vagueness, as I have been arguing throughout, need not pose a problem, need not be in any sense whatsoever a defect, except for one philosophically pre-determined that it shall do and be so.[15] Vagueness does not imply non-existence, and nor need it imply that the existence of the vague object only comes at the cost of being wholly and objectionably dependent upon us.

            Games and languages and heaps and baldness are perfectly real. The vague yet important borderlines where candidates shade off into non-cases does not require founding, nor does it require policing by philosophers. Competent language-users can take care of that, as and when they need to, by themselves.

 

            Now for the last throw of the defender of the sorites. Isn’t there still reason to think that there is a sorites paradox, in the cases where other things are equal, in the cases where the case one is dealing with does become something like a pure numbers game (a question of numbers of hairs, or of a transition between colours arrayed in a row, or of picking out the point in an array of people where ‘tallness’ begins, etc.)? When context and conditions are held constant, isn’t there still a philosophical problem to be solved?

            Let us again compare Wittgenstein; this is section 61 of the Remarks on Colour: ‘We are inclined to believe [misleadingly] that the analysis of our colour concepts would lead ultimately to the colours of places in our visual field, which are independent of any spatial or physical interpretation; for here there is neither light nor shadow, nor high-light, etc. etc. .’ I believe that such an inclination, uncomfortably unattractive or risibly old-fashioned as it may sound, lies at the root of the residual, hard-to-oust temptation to believe that there is a live sorites paradox even in cases where there is a pure numbers game or something similar in play. The unattractiveness of such a belief can I think be thrown into sharp relief when one considers the following point: ‘tall’ or ‘heap’ or ‘red’ are tempting candidates for soritical reasoning, but who would want to argue that ‘a lot’ was a source of paradox? It is plainly not; it is plainly context- and purpose-relative. The boundary between ‘a lot’ and ‘not a lot’ is exhausted by the context and purpose of any utterance featuring these terms. But ‘a lot’ IS a pure numbers game. Unlike with ‘heap’, for instance, there is no question of the kind of ‘woodsellers’-type points made earlier being relevant. There is no question of arrangement of the stuff etc. making a difference: if 10 tonnes of sugar is simply called ‘a lot’, then it is a lot whether it is neatly piled up or accidentally spread all over the warehouse floor.

            My psycho-philosophical diagnosis of what happens when we persist in wanting to reason soritically is as follows: we do so because we unwittingly persist in thinking both that there are conditions of application for the term such as the conditions of distribution and of contiguity relevant for the ‘bald’ and ‘heap’ cases, respectively, and in thinking that there are not. Only so long as we fail to see clearly that, when such conditions are eliminated entirely, leaving (e.g.) only the bare numbers (of hairs, of grains) and our particular purposes (a lot of cakes might be 3, whereas a lot of biscuits might be 12 packets’ worth; a lot of sugar in my tea may not be a lot of sugar at the warehouse, etc.), then the appearance of paradox really does vanish, ...only that long, do we persist in being bamboozled by the paradoxes of vagueness. When we simply contemplate number, in the absence of any and all conditions of distribution and contiguity, there is no question of that number being ‘a lot’ or ‘a little’. The problem comes -- there starts to feel like a paradox -- when we start to include such conditions in our considerations, so as to have a problem at all, but yet want to eliminate them entirely (as ‘impure’?) from the answers we give to the pressing questions that then start to (at least seem to) arise: is this a heap, or not? Is this man bald, or not? Is this worm fat, or not? Considerations of context are through-and-through inevitable, as soon as one has allowed conditions of distribution and contiguity to enter into one’s considerations at all; but yet we are tempted to look for a philosophical answer to the paradox (e.g. the claim that vagueness is merely epistemic; and/or that our language is in itself flawed; etc.) that can transcend what, following Wittgenstein and Garfinkel,[16] I want to suggest are utterly unavoidable and normally-utterly-unproblematic indexical features of our utterances, our practices.

            In short, it only looks like there is the paradox of the heap so long as we -- unawarely -- (and absurdly) want the term ‘heap’ to be both context-bound and context-independent in its use.

            Sainsbury’s (representative, standard) failure to complicate the alleged sorites paradox of colour by considering actual instances of use of colour-terms, and by considering actual instances (which will vary) of encounter with and use of colour-charts and the like, is prototypical. There is no interesting sorites paradox to be garnered from imagining an imaginary colour-chart. One has rather to imagine one actually being looked at, employed. When one does so, then it becomes much easier for instance to imagine aspect-shifts (which might come at various points, depending on circumstances) in the colour one was looking at, such that one would say of two shades that might be abstractly indistinguishable that the point of transition between (say) red and orange happened there. That is: I might well not be making any kind of mistake or producing any kind of myth, if I were to judge, if forced to pronounce on the matter, that a certain point in a real colour-chart was where the transition from red to orange was effected. (And the exercise would be less likely to feel merely forced, if my judgement was consequential: e.g. if it were part of a set of decisions on a colour-scheme for a redesign of the Philosophy Department building.)  Even if, were I to be presented with the two shades either side of the transition-point I picked, isolated, in a psychological experiment, I could not distinguish them from one another.

            The same with height: [17] If I were presented with two men one of whom was 0.1 of an inch smaller than the other, I would most likely judge either that both were tall or that both were small (Though the qualification -- ‘most likely’ -- is needed, for it would depend on the purpose). If I were to judge both as tall, and you were to judge both as small, there is not yet a paradox any more than there is if one of us thinks three sugars in a cup of tea a lot and the other doesn’t. And if we lined up a whole lot of men in a great long line, and their height gradually dropped, and everything else stayed the same (because of course in the real world girth might affect judgements of tallness, etc.), then there would still not need to be any paradox: at some point, if one didn’t simply reject the whole exercise as artificial and meaningless, one would no doubt judge that there was no longer tallness in the man before us, even if the difference between the two men between whom one drew the line would, IF THE TWO WERE CONSIDERED IN ISOLATION, be insignificant or even imperceptible. Given that the two were NOT being considered in isolation, there need be no paradox.

            In sum, as Wittgenstein argues extremely powerfully between PI section 65 and 88, there need be no enduring puzzle around vagueness, if only we do not trap ourselves into one. There remain of course contexts in which we don’t really know how to apply an expression, but all this tells us is that our expressions don’t carry membership conditions with them from the abstract into the concrete. There may sometimes not be a univocal and unequivocal answer to the question ‘Is he bald, or not?’, or ‘Is this a heap, or not?’ But why should this surprise us? Any more than it surprises us or dissatisfies us, outside the priggish philosopher’s study, to hear people saying things like, ‘Well, he’s a bit bald’, or, simply, ‘Yes and no’.[18]

 



[1] E.g. It is given no role whatsoever in R.M. Sainsbury’s respected textbook treatment, (in chapter 2 of) his Paradoxes (Cambridge: C.U.P., 1995).

[2] Transl. Anscombe, Berkeley: U Cal. Press, 1977, Part I, section 50. I have emended the translation slightly. See also sections 63, 67 and 59.

[3] Section 56.

[4] For explication of what this means, see for instance Gordon Baker’s “Wittgenstein on metaphysical/everyday use”, Phil Quarterly Vol. 52 (July ‘02), 290-302, reprinted in his Wittgenstein’s Method (Oxford: Blackwell, 2004).

I am not, of course, entertaining or suggesting the risible claim that people never reason soritically to the point of paradox outside Philosophy Departments; I am however suggesting that people do not end up reasoning soritically to the point of paradox  once they have overcome metaphysical confusion and abstractions. When people reason soritically in everyday life, the reasoning is most typically brought to an end by their interlocutors responding at some point (roughly) that a point has been stretched beyond breaking-point, that they have taken their argument too far.

[5] See Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics (Oxford: Blackwell, 1978 (1956)), Part 1 sections 140-153, especially 149-150.

Alice Crary gives these people (if that is the right word -- see below) the potentially more fruitful name, ‘mathematical strangers’. See her powerful discussion in “Wittgenstein and political philosophy”, The New Wittgenstein (eds. Crary and Read, London: Routledge, 2000).

[6] And that are already clear in Crary’s (ibid.), and in David Cerbone’s deeply-intriguing “How to do things with wood”, also in Crary and Read (ibid.).

[7] For Sainsbury (ibid.), presumably, the woodsellers would be this, or at best (!) plain stupid. If it is clear and indubitable that only the number of grains or planks matters (and not their arrangement), as Sainsbury very much implies, then the woodsellers are simply wrong. But sometimes, whether something is a heap (or whatever vague term you please) matters; it is not only the quantity of matter that matters. For example, slightly fancifully but not I think absurdly: if there were a democratically-agreed scheme for bald men to be compensated for their allegedly-lower quality of life, it would presumably be their baldness (or otherwise), and not the sheer number of hairs on their head, that was considered to be to the point. A broadly supervaluational account -- suitably deflated by a broadly-Wittgensteinian emphasis on context and practice -- such as that offered by David Houghton (in his “Vagueness, stipulation and context”, UEA Papers in Philosophy New Series no.11 (2000), pp.1-24) may help at this point, in enabling us to recover the ordinary. That is, to see through our philosophical bewitchment, and to see clearly (again) how we can reliably and (crucially) purpose-relatively judge that such-and-such is or is not bald, without having to solve ‘the sorites paradox’ in the abstract.

[8] As exposed by, for example, Davidson, “On the very idea of a conceptual scheme” (in Inquiries into truth and interpretation (Cambridge: C.U.P., 1983)); though, contra Davidson, I think that some of those who he criticizes as conceptual relativists, notably Kuhn, are in fact quite consonant with the line of thought I am sketching in this paper. For detail on how to interpret Kuhn as largely invulnerable to correct Davidsonian reasoning, see my Kuhn (Oxford: Polity, 2002, joint with W. Sharrock).

[9] See the discussion below of Conant et al on Wittgenstein (and Frege) on “a hitherto unknown kind of madness” : ‘logically alien thought’.

[10] See again Crary’s and Cerbone’s papers, for a forceful account of the limitation.

[11] The ‘view’ which I seem to be putting forward here may itself seem oxymoronic or radically confused. I shall attempt to show below that it is not, in part by attempting to show that it is not well-read as a view, at all.

[12] Unless perhaps by ‘quietism’ one means to index a line of thought such as that of Cerbone at the close of his (op. cit.).

[13] Philosophical Investigations (Oxford: Blackwell, 1958 (1953); henceforth PI) section 65; underlining mine.

[14] Call this the truth in essentialism, if you like. Hopefully, this ‘truth’ is ‘woolly’ and contentless and ‘question-begging’ enough to seem as trivial and uncontroversial as I mean it to sound.

[15] On this, see especially Wittgenstein’s masterly discussion in for instance sections 68-71, 76-7, 80-84, & 88, of PI.

[16] Harold Garfinkel, the founder of the anti-social-science of ‘ethnomethodology’; see e.g. his Studies in Ethnomethodology (Cambridge: Polity, 1984 (1967)); see also expository work on ethnomethodology and indexicality etc. by Mike Lynch, Wes Sharrock and Rod Watson.

[17] See p. 23 of Sainsbury’s (op.cit.).

[18] My thanks to the members of the Philosophy Evening Reading Group at UEA, especially to John Collins, Cathy Osborne and Nadine Cipa.